Book One: Preliminary Survey

Chapter 1

Introduction

    1. Political economy or economics is a study of mankind in
the ordinary business of life; it examines that part of
individual and social action which is most closely connected with
the attainment and with the use of the material requisites of
wellbeing.
    Thus it is on the one side a study of wealth; and on the
other, and more important side, a part of the study of man. For
man's character has been moulded by his every-day work, and the
material resources which he thereby procures, more than by any
other influence unless it be that of his religious ideals; and
the two great forming agencies of the world's history have been
the religious and the economic. Here and there the ardour of the
military or the artistic spirit has been for a while predominant:
but religious and economic influences have nowhere been displaced
from the front rank even for a time; and they have nearly always
been more important than all others put together. Religious
motives are more intense than economic, but their direct action
seldom extends over so large a part of life. For the business by
which a person earns his livelihood generally fills his thoughts
during by far the greater part of those hours in which his mind
is at its best; during them his character is being formed by the
way in which he uses his faculties in his work, by the thoughts
and the feelings which it suggests, and by his relations to his
associates in work, his employers or his employees.
    And very often the influence exerted on a person's character
by the amount of his income is hardly less, if it is less, than
that exerted by the way in which it is earned. It may make little
difference to the fulness of life of a family whether its yearly
income is £1000 or £5000; but it makes a very great difference
whether the income is £30 or £150: for with £150 the family has,
with £30 it has not, the material conditions of a complete life.
It is true that in religion, in the family affections and in
friendship, even the poor may find scope for many of those
faculties which are the source of the highest happiness. But the
conditions which surround extreme poverty, especially in densely
crowded places, tend to deaden the higher faculties. Those who
have been called the Residuum of our large towns have little
opportunity for friendship; they know nothing of the decencies
and the quiet, and very little even of the unity of family life;
and religion often fails to reach them. No doubt their physical,
mental, and moral ill-health is partly due to other causes than
poverty: but this is the chief cause.
    And, in addition to the Residuum, there are vast numbers of
people both in town and country who are brought up with
insufficient food, clothing, and house-room; whose education is
broken off early in order that they may go to work for wages; who
thenceforth are engaged during long hours in exhausting toil with
imperfectly nourished bodies, and have therefore no chance of
developing their higher mental faculties. Their life is not
necessarily unhealthy or unhappy. Rejoicing in their affections
towards God and man, and perhaps even possessing some natural
refinement of feeling, they may lead lives that are far less
incomplete than those of many, who have more material wealth.
But, for all that, their poverty is a great and almost unmixed
evil to them. Even when they are well, their weariness often
amounts to pain, while their pleasures are few; and when sickness
comes, the suffering caused by poverty increases tenfold. And,
though a contented spirit may go far towards reconciling them to
these evils, there are others to which it ought not to reconcile
them. Overworked and undertaught, weary and careworn, without
quiet and without leisure, they have no chance of making the best
of their mental faculties.
    Although then some of the evils which commonly go with
poverty are not its necessary consequences; yet, broadly
speaking, "the destruction of the poor is their poverty," and the
study of the causes of poverty is the study of the causes of the
degradation of a large part of mankind.
    2. Slavery was regarded by Aristotle as an ordinance of
nature, and so probably was it by the slaves themselves in olden
time. The dignity of man was proclaimed by the Christian
religion: it has been asserted with increasing vehemence during
the last hundred years: but, only through the spread of education
during quite recent times, are we beginning to feel the full
import of the phrase. Now at last we are setting ourselves
seriously to inquire whether it is necessary that there should be
any so-called "lower classes" at all: that is, whether there need
be large numbers of people doomed from their birth to hard work
in order to provide for others the requisites of a refined and
cultured life; while they themselves are prevented by their
poverty and toil from having any share or part in that life.
    The hope that poverty and ignorance may gradually be
extinguished, derives indeed much support from the steady
progress of the working classes during the nineteenth century.
The steam-engine has relieved them of much exhausting and
degrading toil; wages have risen; education has been improved and
become more general; the railway and the printing-press have
enabled members of the same trade in different parts of the
country to communicate easily with one another, and to undertake
and carry out broad and far-seeing lines of policy; while the
growing demand for intelligent work has caused the artisan
classes to increase so rapidly that they now outnumber those
whose labour is entirely unskilled. A great part of the artisans
have ceased to belong to the "lower classes" in the sense in
which the term was originally used; and some of them already lead
a more refined and noble life than did the majority of the upper
classes even a century ago.
    This progress has done more than anything else to give
practical interest to the question whether it is really
impossible that all should start in the world with a fair chance
of leading a cultured life, free from the pains of poverty and
the stagnating influences of excessive mechanical toil; and this
question is being pressed to the front by the growing earnestness
of the age. The question cannot be fully answered by economic
science. For the answer depends partly on the moral and political
capabilities of human nature, and on these matters the economist
has no special means of information: he must do as others do, and
guess as best he can. But the answer depends in a great measure
upon facts and inferences, which are within the province of
economics; and this it is which gives to economic studies their
chief and their highest interest.
    3. It might have been expected that a science, which deals
with questions so vital for the wellbeing of mankind, would have
engaged the attention of many of the ablest thinkers of every
age, and be now well advanced towards maturity. But the fact is
that the number of scientific economists has always been small
relatively to the difficulty of the work to be done; so that the
science is still almost in its infancy. One cause of this is that
the bearing of economics on the higher wellbeing of man has been
overlooked. Indeed, a science which has wealth for its
subject-matter, is often repugnant at first sight to many
students; for those who do most to advance the boundaries of
knowledge, seldom care much about the possession of wealth for
its own sake.
    But a more important cause is that many of those conditions
of industrial life, and of those methods of production,
distribution and consumption, with which modern economic science
is concerned, are themselves only of recent date. It is indeed
true that the change in substance is in some respects not so
great as the change in outward form; and much more of modern
economic theory, than at first appears, can be adapted to the
conditions of backward races. But unity in substance, underlying
many varieties of form, is not easy to detect; and changes in
form have had the effect of making writers in all ages profit
less than they otherwise might have done by the work of their
predecessors.
    The economic conditions of modern life, though more complex,
are in many ways more definite than those of earlier times.
Business is more clearly marked off from other concerns; the
rights of individuals as against others and as against the
community are more sharply defined; and above all the
emancipation from custom, and the growth of free activity, of
constant forethought and restless enterprise, have given a new
precision and a new prominence to the causes that govern the
relative values of different things and different kinds of
labour.
    4. It is often said that the modern forms of industrial life
are distinguished from the earlier by being more competitive. But
this account is not quite satisfactory. The strict meaning of
competition seems to be the racing of one person against another,
with special reference to bidding for the sale or purchase of
anything. This kind of racing is no doubt both more intense and
more widely extended than it used to be: but it is only a
secondary, and one might almost say, an accidental consequence
from the fundamental characteristics of modern industrial life.
    There is no one term that will express these characteristics
adequately. They are, as we shall presently see, a certain
independence and habit of choosing one's own course for oneself,
a self-reliance; a deliberation and yet a promptness of choice
and judgment, and a habit of forecasting the future and of
shaping one's course with reference to distant aims. They may and
often do cause people to compete with one another; but on the
other hand they may tend, and just now indeed they are tending,
in the direction of co-operation and Combination of all kinds
good and evil. But these tendencies towards collective ownership
and collective action are quite different from those of earlier
times, because they are the result not of custom, not of any
passive drifting into association with one's neighbours, but of
free choice by each individual of that line of conduct which
after careful deliberation seems to him the best suited for
attaining his ends, whether they are selfish or unselfish.
    The term "competition" has gathered about it evil savour, and
has come to imply a certain selfishness and indifference to the
wellbeing of others. Now it is true that there is less deliberate
selfishness in early than in modern forms of industry; but there
is also less deliberate unselfishness. It is deliberateness, and
not selfishness, that is the characteristic of the modern age.
    For instance, while custom in a primitive society extends the
limits of the family, and prescribes certain duties to one's
neighbours which fall into disuse in a later civilization, it
also prescribes an attitude of hostility to strangers. In a
modern society the obligations of family kindness become more
intense, though they are concentrated on a narrower area; and
neighbours are put more nearly on the same footing with
strangers. In ordinary dealings with both of them the standard of
fairness and honesty is lower than in some of the dealings of a
primitive people with their neighbours: but it is much higher
than in their dealings with strangers. Thus it is the ties of
neighbourhood alone that have been relaxed: the ties of family
are in many ways stronger than before, family affection leads to
much more self-sacrifice and devotion than it used to do; and
sympathy with those who are strangers to us is a growing source
of a kind of deliberate unselfishness, that never existed before
the modern age. That country which is the birthplace of modern
competition devotes a larger part of its income than any other to
charitable uses, and spent twenty millions on purchasing the
freedom of the slaves in the West Indies.
    In every age poets and social reformers have tried to
stimulate the people of their own time to a nobler life by
enchanting stories of the virtues of the heroes of old. But
neither the records of history nor the contemporary observation
of backward races, when carefully studied, give any support to
the doctrine that man is on the whole harder and harsher than he
was; or that he was ever more willing than he is now to sacrifice
his own happiness for the benefit of others in cases where custom
and law have left him free to choose his own course. Among races,
whose intellectual capacity seems not to have developed in any
other direction, and who have none of the originating power of
the modern business man, there will be found many who show an
evil sagacity in driving a hard bargain in a market even with
their neighbours. No traders are more unscrupulous in taking
advantage of the necessities of the unfortunate than are the
corn-dealers and money-lenders of the East.
    Again, the modern era has undoubtedly given new openings for
dishonesty in trade. The advance of knowledge has discovered new
ways of making things appear other than they are, and has
rendered possible many new forms of adulteration. The producer is
now far removed from the ultimate consumer; and his wrong-doings
are not visited with the prompt and sharp punishment which falls
on the head of a person who, being bound to live and die in his
native village, plays a dishonest trick on one of his neighbours.
The opportunities for knavery are certainly more numerous than
they were; but there is no reason for thinking that people avail
themselves of a larger proportion of such opportunities than they
used to do. On the contrary, modern methods of trade imply habits
of trustfulness on the one side and a power of resisting
temptation to dishonesty on the other, which do not exist among a
backward people. Instances of simple truth and personal fidelity
are met with under all social conditions: but those who have
tried to establish a business of modern type in a backward
country find that they can scarcely ever depend on the native
population for filling posts of trust. It is even more difficult
to dispense with imported assistance for work, which calls for a
strong moral character, than for that which requires great skill
and mental ability. Adulteration and fraud in trade were rampant
in the middle ages to an extent that is very astonishing, when we
consider the difficulties of wrong-doing without detection at
that time.
    In every stage of civilization, in which the power of money
has been prominent, poets in verse and prose have delighted to
depict a past truly "Golden Age," before the pressure of mere
material gold had been felt. Their idyllic pictures have been
beautiful, and have stimulated noble imaginations and resolves;
but they have had very little historical truth. Small communities
with simple wants for which the bounty of nature has made
abundant provision, have indeed sometimes been nearly free from
care about their material needs, and have not been tempted to
sordid ambitions. But whenever we can penetrate to the inner life
of a crowded population under primitive conditions in our own
time, we find more want, more narrowness, and more hardness than
was manifest at a distance: and we never find a more widely
diffused comfort alloyed by less suffering than exists in the
western world to-day. We ought therefore not to brand the forces,
which have made modern civilization, by a name which suggests
evil.
    It is perhaps not reasonable that such a suggestion should
attach to the term "competition"; but in fact it does. In fact,
when competition is arraigned, its anti-social forms are made
prominent; and care is seldom taken to inquire whether there are
not other forms of it, which are so essential to the maintenance
of energy and spontaneity, that their cessation might probably be
injurious on the balance to social wellbeing. The traders or
producers, who find that a rival is offering goods at a lower
price than will yield them a good profit, are angered at his
intrusion, and complain of being wronged; even though it may be
true that those who buy the cheaper goods are in greater need
than themselves, and that the energy and resourcefulness of their
rival is a social gain. In many cases the "regulation of
competition" is a misleading term, that veils the formation of a
privileged class of producers, who often use their combined force
to frustrate the attempts of an able man to rise from a lower
class than their own. Under the pretext of repressing antisocial
competition, they deprive him of the liberty of carving out for
himself a new career, where the services rendered by him to the
consumers of the commodity would be greater than the injuries,
that he inflicts on the relatively small group which objects to
his competition.
    If competition is contrasted with energetic co-operation in
unselfish work for the public good, then even the best forms of
competition are relatively evil; while its harsher and meaner
forms are hateful. And in a world in which all men were perfectly
virtuous, competition would be out of place; but so also would be
private property and every form of private right. Men would think
only of their duties; and no one would desire to have a larger
share of the comforts and luxuries of life than his neighbours.
Strong producers could easily bear a touch of hardship; so they
would wish that their weaker neighbours, while producing less
should consume more. Happy in this thought, they would work for
the general good with all the energy, the inventiveness, and the
eager initiative that belonged to them; and mankind would be
victorious in contests with nature at every turn. Such is the
Golden Age to which poets and dreamers may look forward. But in
the responsible conduct of affairs, it is worse than folly to
ignore the imperfections which still cling to human nature.
    History in general, and especially the history of socialistic
ventures, shows that ordinary men are seldom capable of pure
ideal altruism for any considerable time together; and that the
exceptions are to be found only when the masterful fervour of a
small band of religious enthusiasts makes material concerns to
count for nothing in comparison with the higher faith.
    No doubt men, even now, are capable of much more unselfish
service than they generally render: and the supreme aim of the
economist is to discover how this latent social asset can be
developed most quickly, and turned to account most wisely. But he
must not decry competition in general, without analysis: he is
bound to retain a neutral attitude towards any particular
manifestation of it until he is sure that, human nature being
what it is, the restraint of competition would not be more
anti-social in its working than the competition itself.
    We may conclude then that the term "competition" is not well
suited to describe the special characteristics of industrial life
in the modern age. We need a term that does not imply any moral
qualities, whether good or evil, but which indicates the
undisputed fact that modern business and industry are
characterized by more self-reliant habits, more forethought, more
deliberate and free choice. There is not any one term adequate
for this purpose: but Freedom of Industry and Enterprise, or more
shortly, Economic Freedom, points in the right direction; and it
may be used in the absence of a better. Of course this deliberate
and free choice may lead to a certain departure from individual
freedom when co-operation or combination seems to offer the best
route to the desired end. The questions how far these deliberate
forms of association are likely to destroy the freedom in which
they had their origin and how far they are likely to be conducive
to the public weal, lie beyond the scope of the present
volume.(1*)
    5. This introductory chapter was followed in earlier editions
by two short sketches: the one related to the growth of free
enterprise and generally of economic freedom, and the other to
the growth of economic science. They have no claim to be
systematic histories, however compressed; they aim only at
indicating some landmarks on the routes by which economic
structure and economic thought have travelled to their present
position. They are now transferred to Appendices A and B at the
end of this volume, partly because their full drift can best be
seen after some acquaintance has been made with the
subject-matter of economics; and partly because in the twenty
years, which have elapsed since they were first written, public
opinion as to the position which the study of economic and social
science should hold in a liberal education has greatly developed.
There is less need now than formerly to insist that the economic
problems of the present generation derive much of their
subject-matter from technical and social changes that are of
recent date, and that their form as well as their urgency assume
throughout the effective economic freedom of the mass of the
people.
    The relations of many ancient Greeks and Romans with the
slaves of their households were genial and humane. But even in
Attica the physical and moral wellbeing of the great body of the
inhabitants was not accepted as a chief aim of the citizen.
Ideals of life were high, but they concerned only a. few. and the
doctrine of value, which is full of complexities in the modern
age, could then have been worked out on a plan; such as could be
conceived to-day, only if nearly all manual work were superseded
by automatic machines which required merely a definite allowance
of steam-power and materials, and had no concern with the
requirements of a full citizen's life. Much of modern economics
might indeed have been anticipated in the towns of the Middle
Ages, in which an intelligent and daring spirit was for the first
time combined with patient industry. But they were not left to
work out their career in peace; and the world had to wait for the
dawn of the new economic era till a whole nation was ready for
the ordeal of economic freedom.
    England especially was gradually prepared for the task; but
towards the end of the eighteenth century, the changes, which had
so far been slow and gradual, suddenly became rapid and violent.
Mechanical inventions, the concentration of industries, and a
system of manufacturing on a large scale for distant markets
broke up the old traditions of industry, and left everyone to
bargain for himself as best he might; and at the same time they
stimulated an increase of population for which no provision had
been made beyond standing-room in factories and workshops. Thus
free competition, or rather, freedom of industry and enterprise,
was set loose to run, like a huge untrained monster, its wayward
course. The abuse of their new power by able but uncultured
business men led to evils on every side; it unfitted mothers for
their duties, it weighed down children with overwork and disease;
and in many places it degraded the race. Meanwhile the kindly
meant recklessness of the poor law did even more to lower the
moral and physical energy of Englishmen than the hardhearted
recklessness of the manufacturing discipline: for by depriving
the people of those qualities which would fit them for the new
order of things, it increased the evil and diminished the good
caused by the advent of free enterprise.
    And yet the time at which free enterprise was showing itself
in an unnaturally harsh form, was the very time in which
economists were most lavish in their praises of it. This was
partly because they saw clearly, what we of this generation have
in a great measure forgotten, the cruelty of the yoke of custom
and rigid ordinance which it had displaced; and partly because
the general tendency of Englishmen at the time was to hold that
freedom in all matters, political and social, was worth having at
every cost except the loss of security. But partly also it was
that the productive forces which free enterprise was giving o the
nation were the only means by which it could offer a successful
resistance to Napoleon. Economists therefore treated free
enterprise not indeed as an unmixed good, but as a less evil than
such regulation as was practicable at the time.
    Adhering to the lines of thought that had been started
chiefly by medieval traders, and continued by French and English
philosophers in the latter half of the eighteenth century,
Ricardo and his followers developed a theory of the action of
free enterprise (or, as they said, free competition), which
contained many truths, that will be probably important so long as
the world exists. Their work was wonderfully complete within the
narrow area which it covered. But much of the best of it consists
of problems relating to rent and the value of corn: - problems on
the solution of which the fate of England just then seemed to
depend; but many of which, in the particular form in which they
were worked out by Ricardo, have very little direct bearing on
the present state of things.
    A good deal of the rest of their work was narrowed by its
regarding too exclusively the peculiar condition of England at
that time; and this narrowness has caused a reaction. So that
now, when more experience, more leisure, and greater material
resources have enabled us to bring free enterprise somewhat under
control, to diminish its power of doing evil and increase its
power of doing good, there is growing up among many economists a
sort of spite against it. Some even incline to exaggerate its
evils, and attribute to it the ignorance and suffering, which are
the results either of tyranny and oppression in past ages, or of
the misunderstanding and mismanagement of economic freedom.
    Intermediate between these two extremes are the great body of
economists who, working on parallel lines in many different
countries, are bringing to their studies an unbiassed desire to
ascertain the truth, and a willingness to go through with the
long and heavy work by which alone scientific results of any
value can be obtained. Varieties of mind, of temper, of training
and of opportunities lead them to work in different ways, and to
give their chief attention to different parts of the problem. All
are bound more or less to collect and arrange facts and
statistics relating to past and present times; and all are bound
to occupy themselves more or less with analysis and reasoning on
the basis of those facts which are ready at hand: but some find
the former task the more attractive and absorbing, and others the
latter. This division of labour, however, implies not opposition,
but harmony of purpose. The work of all adds something or other
to that knowledge, which enables us to understand the influences
exerted on the quality and tone of man's life by the manner in
which he earns his livelihood, and by the character of that
livelihood.

NOTES:

1. They occupy a considerable place in the forthcoming volume on
Industry and Trade.

Chapter 2

The Substance of Economics

    1. Economics is a study of men as they live and move and
think in the ordinary business of life. But it concerns itself
chiefly with those motives which affect, most powerfully and most
steadily, man's conduct in the business part of his life.
Everyone who is worth anything carries his higher nature with him
into business; and, there as elsewhere, he is influenced by his
personal affections, by his conceptions of duty and his reverence
for high ideals. And it is true that the best energies of the
ablest inventors and organizers of improved methods and
appliances are stimulated by a noble emulation more than by any
love of wealth for its own sake. But, for all that, the steadiest
motive to ordinary business work is the desire for the pay which
is the material reward of work. The pay may be on its way to be
spent selfishly or unselfishly, for noble or base ends; and here
the variety of human nature comes into play. But the motive is
supplied by a definite amount of money: and it is this definite
and exact money measurement of the steadiest motives in business
life, which has enabled economics far to outrun every other
branch of the study of man. Just as the chemist's fine balance
has made chemistry more exact than most other physical sciences;
so this economist's balance, rough and imperfect as it is, has
made economics more exact than any other branch of social
science. But of course economics cannot be compared with the
exact physical sciences: for it deals with the ever changing and
subtle forces of human nature.(1*)
    The advantage which economics has over other branches of
social science appears then to arise from the fact that its
special field of work gives rather larger opportunities for exact
methods than any other branch. It concerns itself chiefly with
those desires, aspirations and other affections of human nature,
the outward manifestations of which appear as incentives to
action in such a form that the force or quantity of the
incentives can be estimated and measured with some approach to
accuracy., and which therefore are in some degree amenable to
treatment by scientific machinery. An opening is made for the
methods and the tests of science as soon as the force of a
person's motives - not the motives themselves - can be
approximately measured by the sum of money, which he will just
give up in order to secure a desired satisfaction; or again by
the sum which is just required to induce him to undergo a certain
fatigue.
    It is essential to note that the economist does not claim to
measure any affection of the mind in itself, or directly; but
only indirectly through its effect. No one can compare and
measure accurately against one another even his own mental states
at different times: and no one can measure the mental states of
another at all except indirectly and conjecturally by their
effects. Of course various affections belong to man's higher
nature and others to his lower, and are thus different in kind.
But, even if we confine our attention to mere physical pleasures
and pains of the same kind, we find that they can only be
compared indirectly by their effects. In fact, even this
comparison is necessarily to some extent conjectural, unless they
occur to the same person at the same time.
    For instance the pleasures which two persons derive from
smoking cannot be directly compared: nor can even those which the
same person derives from it at different times. But if we find a
man in doubt whether to spend a few pence on a cigar, or a cup of
tea, or on riding home instead of walking home, then we may
follow ordinary usage, and say that he expects from them equal
pleasures.
    If then we wish to compare even physical gratifications, we
must do it not directly, but indirectly by the incentives which
they afford to action. If the desires to secure either of two
pleasures will induce people in similar circumstances each to do
just an hour's extra work, or will induce men in the same rank of
life and with the same means each to pay a shilling for it; we
then may say that those pleasures are equal for our purposes,
because the desires for them are equally strong incentives to
action for persons under similar conditions.
    Thus measuring a mental state, as men do in ordinary life, by
its motor-force or the incentive which it affords to action, no
new difficulty is introduced by the fact that some of the motives
of which we have to take account belong to man's higher nature,
and others to his lower.
    For suppose that the person, whom we saw doubting between
several little gratifications for himself, had thought after a
while of a poor invalid whom he would pass on his way home; and
had spent some time in making up his mind whether he would choose
a physical gratification for himself, or would do a kindly act
and rejoice in another's joy. As his desires turned now towards
the one, now the other, there would be change in the quality of
his mental states; and the philosopher is bound to study the
nature of the change.
    But the economist studies mental states rather through their
manifestations than in themselves; and if he finds they afford
evenly balanced incentives to action, he treats them prima facie
as for his purpose equal. He follows indeed in a more patient and
thoughtful way, and with greater precautions, what everybody is
always doing every day in ordinary life. He does not attempt to
weigh the real value of the higher affections of our nature
against those of our lower: he does not balance the love for
virtue against the desire for agreeable food. He estimates the
incentives to action by their effects just in the same way as
people do in common life. He follows the course of ordinary
conversation, differing from it only in taking more precautions
to make clear the limits of his knowledge as he goes. He reaches
his provisional conclusions by observations of men in general
under given conditions without attempting to fathom the mental
and spiritual characteristics of individuals. But he does not
ignore the mental and spiritual side of life. On the contrary,
even for the narrower uses of economic studies, it is important
to know whether the desires which prevail are such as will help
to build up a strong and righteous character. And in the broader
uses of those studies, when they are being applied to practical
problems, the economist, like every one else, must concern
himself with the ultimate aims of man, and take account of
differences in real value between gratifications that are equally
powerful incentives to action and have therefore equal economic
measures. A study of these measures is only the starting-point of
economics: but it is the starting-point.(2*)
    2. There are several other limitations of the measurement of
motive by money to be discussed. The first of these arises from
the necessity of taking account of the variations in the amount
of pleasure, or other satisfaction, represented by the same sum
of money to different persons and under different circumstances.
    A shilling may measure a greater pleasure (or other
satisfaction) at one time than at another even for the same
person; because money may be more plentiful with him, or because
his sensibility may vary.(3*) And persons whose antecedents are
similar, and who are outwardly like one another, are often
affected in very different ways by similar events. When, for
instance, a band of city school children are sent out for a day's
holiday in the country, it is probable that no two of them derive
from it enjoyment exactly the same in kind, or equal in
intensity. The same surgical operation causes different amounts
of pain to different people. Of two parents who are, so far as we
can tell, equally affectionate, one will suffer much more than
the other from the loss of a favourite son. Some who are not very
sensitive generally are yet specially susceptible to particular
kinds of pleasure and pain; while differences in nature and
education make one man's total capacity for pleasure or pain much
greater than another's.
    It would therefore not be safe to say that any two men with
the same income derive equal benefit from its use; or that they
would suffer equal pain from the same diminution of it. Although
when a tax of £1 is taken from each of two persons having an
income of £300 a year, each will give up that £1 worth of
pleasure (or other satisfaction) which he can most easily part
with, i.e. each will give up what is measured to him by just £1;
yet the intensities of the satisfaction given up may not be
nearly equal.
    Nevertheless, if we take averages sufficiently broad to cause
the personal peculiarities of individuals to counterbalance one
another, the money which people of equal incomes will give to
obtain a benefit or avoid an injury is a good measure of the
benefit or injury. If there are a thousand persons living in
Sheffield, and another thousand in Leeds, each with about £100
a-year, and a tax of £1 is levied on all of them; we may be sure
that the loss of pleasure or other injury which the tax will
cause in Sheffield is of about equal importance with that which
it will cause in Leeds: and anything that increased all the
incomes by £1 would give command over equivalent pleasures and
other benefits in the two towns. This probability becomes greater
still if all of them are adult males engaged in the same trade;
and therefore presumably somewhat similar in sensibility and
temperament, in taste and education. Nor is the probability much
diminished, if we take the family as our unit, and compare the
loss of pleasure that results from diminishing by £1 the income
of each of a thousand families with incomes of £100 a-year in the
two places.
    Next we must take account of the fact that a stronger
incentive will be required to induce a person to pay a given
price for anything if he is poor than if he is rich. A shilling
is the measure of less pleasure, or satisfaction of any kind, to
a rich man than to a poor one. A rich man in doubt whether to
spend a shilling on a single cigar, is weighing against one
another smaller pleasures than a poor man, who is doubting
whether to spend a shilling on a supply of tobacco that will last
him for a month. The clerk with £100 a-year will walk to business
in a much heavier rain than the clerk with £300 a-year; for the
cost of a ride by tram or omnibus measures a greater benefit to
the poorer man than to the richer. If the poorer man spends the
money, he will suffer more from the want of it afterwards than
the richer would. The benefit that is measured in the poorer
man's mind by the cost is greater than that measured by it in the
richer man's mind.
    But this source of error also is lessened when we are able to
consider the actions and the motives of large groups of people.
If we know, for instance, that a bank failure has taken £200,000
from the people of Leeds and £100,000 from those of Sheffield, we
may fairly assume that the suffering caused in Leeds has been
about twice as great as in Sheffield; unless indeed we have some
special reason for believing that the shareholders of the bank in
the one town were a richer class than those in the other; or that
the loss of employment caused by it pressed in uneven proportions
on the working classes in the two towns.
    By far the greater number of the events with which economics
deals affect in about equal proportions all the different classes
of society; so that if the money measures of the happiness caused
by two events are equal, it is reasonable and in accordance with
common usage to regard the amounts of the happiness in the two
cases as equivalent. And, further, as money is likely to be
turned to the higher uses of life in about equal proportions, by
any two large groups of people taken without special bias from
any two parts of the western world, there is even some prima
facie probability that equal additions to their material
resources will make about equal additions to the fulness of life,
and true progress of the human race.
    3. To pass to another point. When we speak of the measurement
of desire by the action to which it forms the incentive, it is
not to be supposed that we assume every action to be deliberate,
and the outcome of calculation. For in this, as in every other
respect, economics takes man just as he is in ordinary life: and
in ordinary life people do not weigh beforehand the results of
every action, whether the impulses to it come from their higher
nature or their lower.(4*)
    Now the side of life with which economics is specially
concerned is that in which man's conduct is most deliberate, and
in which he most often reckons up the advantages and
disadvantages of any particular action before he enters on it.
And further it is that side of his life in which, when he does
follow habit and custom, and proceeds for the moment without
calculation, the habits and customs themselves are most nearly
sure to have arisen from a close and careful watching the
advantages and disadvantages of different courses of conduct.
There will not in general have been any formal reckoning up of
two sides of a balance-sheet: but men going home from their day's
work, or in their social meetings, will have said to one another,
"It did not answer to do this, it would have been better to do
that," and so on. What makes one course answer better than
another, will not necessarily be a selfish gain, nor any material
gain; and it will often have been argued that." though this or
that plan saved a little trouble or a little money, yet it was
not fair to others," and "it made one look mean," or "it made one
feel mean." It is true that when a habit or a custom, which has
grown up under one set of conditions, influences action under
other conditions, there is so far no exact relation between the
effort and the end which is attained by it. In backward countries
there are still many habits and customs similar to those that
lead a beaver in confinement to build himself a dam; they are
full of suggestiveness to the historian, and must be reckoned
with by the legislator. But in business matters in the modern
world such habits quickly die away.
    Thus then the most systematic part of people's lives is
generally that by which they earn their living. The work of all
those engaged in any one occupation can be carefully observed;
general statements can be made about it, and tested by comparison
with the results of other observations; and numerical estimates
can be framed as to the amount of money or general purchasing
power that is required to supply a sufficient motive for them.
    The unwillingness to postpone enjoyment, and thus to save for
future use, is measured by the interest on accumulated wealth
which just affords a sufficient incentive to save for the future.
This measurement presents however some special difficulties, the
study of which must be postponed.
    4. Here, as elsewhere, we must bear in mind that the desire
to make money does not itself necessarily proceed from motives of
a low order, even when it is to be spent on oneself. Money is a
means towards ends, and if the ends are noble, the desire for the
means is not ignoble. The lad who works hard and saves all he
can, in order to be able to pay his way afterwards at a
University, is eager for money; but his eagerness is not ignoble.
In short, money is general purchasing power, and is sought as a
means to all kinds of ends, high as well as low, spiritual as
well as material.(5*)
    Thus though it is true that "money" or "general purchasing
power" or "command over material wealth", is the centre around
which economic science clusters; this is so, not because money or
material wealth is regarded as the main aim of human effort, nor
even as affording the main subject-matter for the study of the
economist, but because in this world of ours it is the one
convenient means of measuring human motive on a large scale. If
the older economists had made this clear, they would have escaped
many grievous misrepresentations; and the splendid teachings of
Carlyle and Ruskin as to the right aims of human endeavour and
the right uses of wealth, would not then have been marred by
bitter attacks on economics, based on the mistaken belief that
that science had no concern with any motive except the selfish
desire for wealth, or even that it inculcated a policy of sordid
selfishness.(6*)
    Again, when the motive to a man's action is spoken of as
supplied by the money which he will earn, it is not meant that
his mind is closed to all other considerations save those of
gain. For even the most purely business relations of life assume
honesty and good faith; while many of them take for granted, if
not generosity, yet at least the absence of meanness, and the
pride which every honest man takes in acquitting himself well.
Again, much of the work by which people earn their living is
pleasurable in itself; and there is truth in the contention of
socialists that more of it might be made so. Indeed even business
work, that seems at first sight unattractive, often yields a
great pleasure by offering scope for the exercise of men's
faculties, and for their instincts of emulation and of power. For
just as a racehorse or an athlete strains every nerve to get in
advance of his competitors, and delights in the strain; so a
manufacturer or a trader is often stimulated much more by the
hope of victory over his rivals than by the desire to add
something to his fortune.(7*)
    5. It has indeed always been the practice of economists to
take careful account of all the advantages which attract people
generally towards an occupation, whether they appear in a money
form or not. Other things being equal, people will prefer an
occupation in which they do not need to soil their hands, in
which they enjoy a good social position, and so on; and since
these advantages affect, not indeed every one exactly in the same
way, but most people in nearly the same way, their attractive
force can be estimated and measured by the money wages to which
they are regarded as equivalent.
    Again, the desire to earn the approval, to avoid the contempt
of those around one is a stimulus to action which often works
with some sort of uniformity in any class of persons at a given
time and place; though local and temporary conditions influence
greatly not only the intensity of the desire for approval, but
also the range of persons whose approval is desired. A
professional man, for instance, or an artisan will be very
sensitive to the approval or disapproval of those in the same
occupation, and care little for that of other people; and there
are many economic problems, the discussion of which would be
altogether unreal, if care were not taken to watch the direction
and to estimate pretty closely the force of motives such as
these.
    As there may be a taint of selfishness in a man's desire to
do what seems likely to benefit his fellow-workers, so there may
be an element of personal pride in his desire that his family
should prosper during his life and after it. But still the family
affections generally are so pure a form of altruism, that their
action might have shown little semblance of regularity, had it
not been for the uniformity in the family relations themselves.
As it is, their action is fairly regular; and it has always been
fully reckoned with by economists, especially in relation to the
distribution of the family income between its various members,
the expenses of preparing children for their future career, and
the accumulation of wealth to be enjoyed after the death of him
by whom it has been earned.
    It is then not the want of will but the want of power, that
prevents economists from reckoning in the action of motives such
as these; and they welcome the fact that some kinds of
philanthropic action can be described in statistical returns, and
can to a certain extent be reduced to law, if sufficiently broad
averages are taken. For indeed there is scarcely any motive so
fitful and irregular, but that some law with regard to it can be
detected by the aid of wide and patient observation. It would
perhaps be possible even now to predict with tolerable closeness
the subscriptions that a population of a hundred thousand
Englishmen of average wealth will give to support hospitals and
chapels and missions; and, in so far as this can be done, there
is a basis for an economic discussion of supply and demand with
reference to the services of hospital nurses, missionaries and
other religious ministers. It will however probably be always
true that the greater part of those actions, which are due to a
feeling of duty and love of one's neighbour, cannot be classed,
reduced to law and measured; and it is for this reason, and not
because they are not based on self-interest, that the machinery
of economics cannot be brought to bear on them.
    6. Perhaps the earlier English economists confined their
attention too much to the motives of individual action. But in
fact economists, like all other students of social science, are
concerned with individuals chiefly as members of the social
organism. As a cathedral is something more than the stones of
which it is made, as a person is something more than a series of
thoughts and feelings, so the life of society is something more
than the sum of the lives of its individual members. It is true
that the action of the whole is made up of that of its
constituent parts; and that in most economic problems the best
starting-point is to be found in the motives that affect the
individual, regarded not indeed as an isolated atom, but as a
member of some particular trade or industrial group; but it is
also true, as German writers have well urged, that economics has
a great and an increasing concern in motives connected with the
collective ownership of property, and the collective pursuit of
important aims. The growing earnestness of the age, the growing
intelligence of the mass of the people, and the growing power of
the telegraph, the press, and other means of communication are
ever widening the scope of collective action for the public good;
and these changes, together with the spread of the co-operative
movement, and other kinds of voluntary association are growing up
under the influence of various motives besides that of pecuniary
gain: they are ever opening to the economist new opportunities of
measuring motives whose action it had seemed impossible to reduce
to any sort of law.   But in fact the variety of motives, the
difficulties of measuring them, and the manner of overcoming
those difficulties are among the chief subjects with which we
shall be occupied in this treatise. Almost every point touched in
the present chapter will need to be discussed in fuller detail
with reference to some one or more of the leading problems of
economics.
    7. To conclude provisionally: economists study the actions of
individuals, but study them in relation to social rather than
individual life; and therefore concern themselves but little with
personal peculiarities of temper and character. They watch
carefully the conduct of a whole class of people, sometimes the
whole of a nation, sometimes only those living in a certain
district, more often those engaged in some particular trade at
some time and place: and by the aid of statistics, or in other
ways, they ascertain how much money on the average the members of
the particular group, they are watching, are just willing to pay
as the price of a certain thing which they desire, or how much
must be offered to them to induce them to undergo a certain
effort or abstinence that they dislike. The measurement of motive
thus obtained is not indeed perfectly accurate; for if it were,
economics would rank with the most advanced of the physical
sciences; and not, as it actually does, with the least advanced.
    But yet the measurement is accurate enough to enable
experienced persons to forecast fairly well the extent of the
results that will follow from changes in which motives of this
kind are chiefly concerned. Thus, for instance, they can estimate
very closely the payment that will be required to produce an
adequate supply of labour of any grade, from the lowest to the
highest, for a new trade which it is proposed to start in any
place. When they visit a factory of a kind that they have never
seen before, they can tell within a shilling or two a week what
any particular worker is earning, by merely observing how far his
is a skilled occupation and what strain it involves on his
physical, mental and moral faculties. And they can predict with
tolerable certainty what rise of price will result from a given
diminution of the supply of a certain thing, and how that
increased price will react on the supply.
    And, starting from simple considerations of this kind, is
economists go on to analyse the causes which govern the local
distribution of different kinds of industry, the terms on which
people living in distant places exchange their goods with one
another, and so on: and they can explain and predict the ways in
which fluctuations of credit will affect foreign trade; or again
the extent to which the burden of a tax will be shifted from
those on whom it is levied, on to those for whose wants they
cater; and so on.
    In all this they deal with man as he is: not with an abstract
or "economic" man; but a man of flesh and blood. They deal with a
man who is largely influenced by egoistic motives in his business
life to a great extent with reference to them; but who is also
neither above vanity and recklessness, nor below delight in doing
his work well for its own sake, or in sacrificing himself for the
good of his family, his neighbours, or his country; a man who is
not below the love of a virtuous life for its own sake. They deal
with man as he is: but being concerned chiefly with those aspects
of life in which the action of motive is so regular that it can
be predicted, and the estimate of the motor-forces can be
verified by results, they have established their work on a
scientific basis.
    For in the first place, they deal with facts which can be
observed, and quantities which can be measured and recorded; so
that when differences of opinion arise with regard to them, the
differences can be brought to the test of public and
well-established records; and thus science obtains a solid basis
on which to work. In the second place, the problems, which are
grouped as economic, because they relate specially to man's
conduct under the influence of motives that are measurable by a
money price, are found to make a fairly homogeneous group. Of
course they have a great deal of subject-matter in common: that
is obvious from the nature of the case. But, though not so
obvious a priori, it will also be found to be true that there is
a fundamental unity of form underlying all the chief of them; and
that in consequence, by studying them together, the same kind of
economy is gained, as by sending a single postman to deliver all
the letters in a certain street, instead of each one entrusting
his letters to a separate messenger. For the analyses and
organized processes of reasoning that are wanted for any one
group of them, will be found generally useful for other groups.
    The less then we trouble ourselves with scholastic inquiries
as to whether a certain consideration comes within the scope of
economics, the better. If the matter is important let us take
account of it as far as we can. If it is one as to which there
exist divergent opinions, such as cannot be brought to the test
of exact and well-ascertained knowledge; if it is one on which
the general machinery of economic analysis and reasoning cannot
get any grip, then let us leave it aside in our purely economic
studies. But let us do so simply because the attempt to include
it would lessen the certainty and the exactness of our economic
knowledge without any commensurate gain; and remembering always
that some sort of account of it must be taken by our ethical
instincts and our common sense, when they as ultimate arbiters
come to apply to practical issues the knowledge obtained and
arranged by economics and other sciences.

NOTES:

1. Some remarks on the relation of economics to the sum total of
social science will be found in Appendix C, sections 1, 2.

2. The objections raised by some philosophers to speaking of two
pleasures as equal, under any circumstances, seem to apply only
to uses of the phrase other than those with which the economist
is concerned. It has however unfortunately happened that the
customary uses of economic terms have sometimes suggested the
belief that economists are adherents of the philosophical system
of Hedonism or of Utilitarianism. For, while they have generally
taken for granted that the greatest pleasures are those which
come with the endeavour to do one's duty, they have spoken of
"pleasures" and "pains" as supplying the motives to all action;
and they have thus brought themselves under the censure of those
philosophers, with whom it is a matter of principle to insist
that the desire to do one's duty is a different thing from a
desire for the pleasure which, if one happens to think of the
matter at all, one may expect from doing it; though perhaps it
may be not incorrectly described as a desire for
"self-satisfaction" or "the satisfaction of the permanent self."
(See for instance T.H. Green, Prolegomena to Ethics, pp. 165-6)
    It is clearly not the part of economics to appear to take a
side in ethical controversy: and since there is a general
agreement that all incentives to action, in so far as they are
conscious desires at all, may without impropriety be spoken of
shortly as desires for "satisfaction," it may perhaps be well to
use this word instead of "pleasure," when occasion arises for
referring to the aims of all desires, whether appertaining to
man's higher or lower nature. The simple antithesis to
satisfaction is "dissatisfaction": but perhaps it may be well to
use the shorter and equally colourless word "detriment". in its
place.
    It may however be noted that some followers of Bentham
(though perhaps not Bentham himself) made this large use of "pain
and pleasure" serve as a bridge by which to pass from
individualistic Hedonism to a complete ethical creed, without
recognizing the necessity for the introduction of an independent
major premiss; and for such a premiss the necessity would appear
to be absolute, although opinions will perhaps always differ as
to its form. Some will regard it as the Categorical Imperative;
while others will regard it as a simple belief that, whatever be
the origin of our moral instincts, their indications are borne
out by a Verdict of the experience of mankind to the effect that
true happiness is not to be had without self-respect, and that
self-respect is to be had only on the condition of endeavouring
so to live as to promote the progress of the human race.

3. Compare Edgeworth's Mathematical Psychics.

4. This is specially true of that group of gratifications, which
is sometimes named "the pleasures of the chase." They include not
only the light-hearted emulation of games and pastimes, of hunts
and steeplechases, but the more serious contests of professional
and business life: and they will occupy a good deal of our
attention in discussions of the causes that govern wages and
profits, and forms of industrial organization.
    Some people are of wayward temperament, and could give no
good account even to themselves of the motives of their action.
But if a man is steadfast and thoughtful, even his impulses are
the products of habits which he has adopted more or less
deliberately. And, whether these impulses are an expression of
his higher nature or not; whether they spring from mandates of
his conscience, the pressure of social connection, or the claims
of his bodily wants, he yields a certain relative precedence to
them without reflection now, because on previous occasions he has
decided deliberately to yield that relative precedence. The
predominant attractiveness of one course of action over others,
even when not the result of calculation at the time, is the
product of more or less deliberate decisions made by him before
in somewhat similar cases.

5. See an admirable essay by Cliffe Leslie on The Love of Money.
We do indeed hear of people who pursue money for its own sake
without caring for what it will purchase, especially at the end
of a long life spent in business: but in this as in other cases
the habit of doing a thing is kept up after the purpose for which
it was originally done has ceased to exist. The possession of
wealth gives such people a feeling of power over their
fellow-creatures, and insures them a sort of envious respect in
which they find a bitter but strong pleasure.

6. In fact a world can be conceived in which there is a science
of economics very much like our own, but in it there is no money
of any sort. See Appendices B, sec. 8 and D, sec. 2.

7. Some remarks on the large scope of economics as conceived in
Germany will be found in Appendix D, sec. 3.

Chapter 3

Economic Generalization or Laws

    1. It is the business of economics, as of almost every other
science, to collect facts, to arrange and interpret them, and to
draw inferences from them. "Observation and description,
definition and classification are the preparatory activities. But
what we desire to reach thereby is a knowledge of the
interdependence of economic phenomena.... Induction and deduction
are both needed for scientific thought as the right and left foot
are both needed for walking."(1*) The methods required for this
twofold work are not peculiar to economics; they are the common
property of all sciences. All the devices for the discovery of
the relations between cause and effect, which are described in
treatises on scientific method, have to be used in their turn by
the economist: there is not any one method of investigation which
can properly be called the method of economics; but every method
must be made serviceable in its proper place, either singly or in
combination with others. And as the number of combinations that
can be made on the chess-board, is so great that probably no two
games exactly alike were ever played; so no two games which the
student plays with nature to wrest from her her hidden truths,
which were worth playing at all, ever made use of quite the same
methods in quite the same way.
    But in some branches of economic inquiry and for some
purposes, it is more urgent to ascertain new facts, than to
trouble ourselves with the mutual relations and explanations of
those which we already have. While in other branches there is
still so much uncertainty as to whether those causes of any event
which lie on the surface and suggest themselves at first are both
true causes of it and the only causes of it, that it is even more
urgently needed to scrutinize our reasoning about facts which we
already know, than to seek for more facts.
    For this and other reasons, there always has been and there
probably always will be a need for the existence side by side of
workers with different aptitudes and different aims, some of whom
give their chief attention to the ascertainment of facts, while
others give their chief attention to scientific analysis; that is
taking to pieces complex facts, and studying the relations of the
several parts to one another and to cognate facts. It is to be
hoped that these two schools will always exist; each doing its
own work thoroughly, and each making use of the work of the
other. Thus best may we obtain sound generalizations as to the
past and trustworthy guidance from it for the future.
    2. Those physical sciences, which have progressed most beyond
the points to which they were brought by the brilliant genius of
the Greeks, are not all of them strictly speaking "exact
sciences." But they all aim at exactness. That is they all aim at
precipitating the result of a multitude of observations into
provisional statements, which are sufficiently definite to be
brought under test by other observations of nature. These
statements, when first put forth, seldom claim a high authority.
But after they have been tested by many independent observations,
and especially after they have been applied successfully in the
prediction of coming events, or of the results of new
experiments, they graduate as laws. A science progresses by
increasing the number and exactness of its laws; by submitting
them to tests of ever increasing severity; and by enlarging their
scope till a single broad law contains and supersedes a number of
narrower laws, which have been shown to be special instances of
it.
    In so far as this is done by any science, a student of it can
in certain cases say with authority greater than his own (greater
perhaps than that of any thinker, however able, who relies on his
own resources and neglects the results obtained by previous
workers), what results are to be expected from certain
conditions, or what are the true causes of a certain known event.
    Although the subject-matter of some progressive physical
sciences is not, at present at least, capable of perfectly exact
measurement; yet their progress depends on the multitudinous
co-operation of armies of workers. They measure their facts and
define their statements as closely as they can: so that each
investigator may start as nearly as possible where those before
him left off. Economics aspires to a place in this group of
sciences: because though its measurements are seldom exact, and
are never final; yet it is ever working to make them more exact,
and thus to enlarge the range of matters on which the individual
student may speak with the authority of his science.
    3. Let us then consider more closely the nature of economic
laws, and their limitations. Every cause has a tendency to
produce some definite result if nothing occurs to hinder it. Thus
gravitation tends to make things fall to the ground: but when a
balloon is full of gas lighter than air, the pressure of the air
will make it rise in spite of the tendency of gravitation to make
it fall. The law of gravitation states how any two things attract
one another. how they tend to move towards one another, and will
'move towards one another if nothing interferes to prevent them.
The law of gravitation is therefore a statement of tendencies.
    It is a very exact statement - so exact that mathematicians
can calculate a Nautical Almanac, which will show the moments at
which each satellite of Jupiter will hide itself behind Jupiter.
They make this calculation for many years beforehand; and
navigators take it to sea, and use it in finding out where they
are. Now there are no economic tendencies which act as steadily
and can be measured as exactly as gravitation can: and
consequently there are no laws of economics which can be compared
for precision with the law of gravitation.
    But let us look at a science less exact than astronomy. The
science of the tides explains how the tide rises and falls twice
a day under the action of the sun and the moon: how there are
strong tides at new and full moon, and weak tides at the moon's
first and third quarter; and how the tide running up into a
closed channel, like that of the Severn, will be very high; and
so on. Thus, having studied the lie of the land and the water all
round the British isles, people can calculate beforehand when the
tide will probably be at its highest on any day at London Bridge
or at Gloucester; and how high it will be there. They have to use
the word probably, which the astronomers do not need to use when
talking about the eclipses of Jupiter's satellites. For, though
many forces act upon Jupiter and his satellites, each one of them
acts in a definite manner which can be predicted beforehand: but
no one knows enough about the weather to be able to say
beforehand how it will act. A heavy downpour of rain in the upper
Thames valley, or a strong north-east wind in the German Ocean,
may make the tides at London Bridge differ a good deal from what
had been expected.
    The laws of economics are to be compared with the laws of the
tides, rather than with the simple and exact law of gravitation.
For the actions of men are so various and uncertain, that the
best statement of tendencies, which we can make in a science of
human conduct, must needs be inexact and faulty. This might be
urged as a reason against making any statements at all on the
subject; but that would be almost to abandon life. Life is human
conduct, and the thoughts and emotions that grow up around it. By
the fundamental impulses of our nature we all-high and low,
learned and unlearned-are in our several degrees constantly
striving to understand the courses of human action, and to shape
them for our purposes, whether selfish or unselfish, whether
noble or ignoble. And since we must form to ourselves some
notions of the tendencies of human action, our choice is between
forming those notions carelessly and forming them carefully. The
harder the task, the greater the need for steady patient inquiry;
for turning to account the experience, that has been reaped by
the more advanced physical sciences; and for framing as best we
can well thought-out estimates, or provisional laws, of the
tendencies of human action.
    4. The term "law" means then nothing more than a general
proposition or statement of tendencies, more or less certain,
more or less definite. Many such statements are made in every
science: but we do not, indeed we can not, give to all of them a
formal character and name them as laws. We must select; and the
selection is directed less by purely scientific considerations
than by practical convenience. If there is any general statement
which we want to bring to bear so often, that the trouble of
quoting it at length, when needed, is greater than that of
burdening the discussion with an additional formal statement and
an additional technical name, then it receives a special name,
otherwise not.(2*)
    Thus a law of social science, or a Social Law, is a statement
of social tendencies; that is, a statement that a certain course
of action may be expected under certain conditions from the
members of a social group.
    Economic laws, or statements of economic tendencies, are
those social laws which relate to branches of conduct in which
the strength of the motives chiefly concerned can be measured by
a money price.
    There is thus no hard and sharp line of division between
those social laws which are, and those which are not, to be
regarded also as economic laws. For there is a continuous
gradation from social laws concerned almost exclusively with
motives that can be measured by price, to social laws in which
such motives have little place; and which are therefore generally
as much less precise and exact than economic laws, as those are
than the laws of the more exact physical sciences.
    Corresponding to the substantive "law" is the adjective
"legal". But this term is used only in connection with "law" in
the sense of an ordinance of government; not in connection with
"law" the sense of a statement of relation between cause and
effect. The adjective used for this purpose is derived from
"norma", a term which is nearly equivalent to "law", and might
perhaps with advantage be substituted for it in scientific
discussions. And following our definition of an economic law, we
may say that the course of action which may be expected under
certain conditions from the members of an industrial group is the
normal action of the members of that group relatively to those
conditions.
    This use of the term Normal has been misunderstood; and it
may be well to say something as to the unity in difference which
underlies various uses of the term. When we talk of a Good man or
a Strong man, we refer to excellence or strength of those
particular physical mental or moral qualities which are indicated
in the context. A strong judge has seldom the same qualities as a
strong rower; a good jockey is not always of exceptional virtue.
In the same way every use of the term normal implies the
predominance of certain tendencies which appear likely to be more
or less steadfast and persistent in their action over those which
are relatively exceptional and intermittent. Illness is an
abnormal condition of man: but a long life passed without any
illness is abnormal. During the melting of the snows, the Rhine
rises above its normal level: but in a cold dry spring when it is
less than usual above that normal level, it may be said to be
abnormally low (for that time of year). In all these cases normal
results are those which may be expected as the outcome of those
tendencies which the context suggests; or, in other words, which
are in accordance with those "statements of tendency", those Laws
or Norms, which are appropriate to the context.
    This is the point of view from which it is said that normal
economic action is that which may be expected in the long run
under certain conditions (provided those conditions are
persistent) from the members of an industrial group. It is normal
that bricklayers in most parts of England are willing to work for
10d. an hour, but refuse to work for 7 d. In Johannesburg it may
be normal that a bricklayer should refuse work at much less than
£1 a day. The normal price of bona fide fresh laid eggs may be
taken to be a penny when nothing is said as to the time of the
year: and yet threepence may be the normal price in town during
January; and twopence may be an abnormally low price then, caused
by "unseasonable" warmth.
    Another misunderstanding to be guarded against arises from
the notion that only those economic results are normal, which are
due to the undisturbed action of free competition. But the term
has often to be applied to conditions in which perfectly free
competition does not exist, and can hardly even be supposed to
exist; and even where free competition is most dominant, the
normal conditions of every facet and tendency will include vital
elements that are not a part of competition nor even akin to it.
Thus, for instance, the normal arrangement of many transactions
in retail and wholesale trade, and on Stock and Cotton Exchanges,
rests on the assumption that verbal contracts, made without
witnesses, will be honourably discharged; and in countries in
which this assumption cannot legitimately be made, some parts of
the Western doctrine of normal value are inapplicable. Again, the
prices of various Stock Exchange securities are affected
"normally" by the patriotic feelings not only of the ordinary
purchasers, but of the brokers themselves: and so on.
    Lastly it is sometimes erroneously supposed that normal
action in economics is that which is right morally. But that is
to be understood only when the context implies that the action is
being judged from the ethical point of view. When we are
considering the facts of the world, as they are, and not as they
ought to be, we shall have to regard as "normal" to the
circumstances in view, much action which we should use our utmost
efforts to stop. For instance, the normal condition of many of
the very poorest inhabitants of a large town is to be devoid of
enterprise, and unwilling to avail themselves of the
opportunities that may offer for a healthier and less squalid
life elsewhere; they have not the strength, physical, mental and
moral, required for working their way out of their miserable
surroundings. The existence of a considerable supply of labour
ready to make match-boxes at a very low rate is normal in the
same way that a contortion of the limbs is a normal result of
taking strychnine. It is one result, a deplorable result, of
those tendencies the laws of which we have to study. This
illustrates one peculiarity which economics shares with a few
other sciences, the nature of the material of which can be
modified by human effort. Science may suggest a moral or
practical precept to modify that nature and thus modify the
action of laws of nature. For instance, economics may suggest
practical means of substituting capable workers for those who can
only do such work as match-box making; as physiology may suggest
measures for so modifying the breeds of cattle that they mature
early, and carry much flesh on light frames. The laws of the
fluctuation of credit and prices have been much altered by
increased powers of prediction.
    Again when "normal" prices are contrasted with temporary or
market prices, the term refers to the dominance in the long run
of certain tendencies under given conditions. But this raises
some difficult questions which may be postponed.(3*)
    5. It is sometimes said that the laws of economics are
"hypothetical". Of course, like every other science, it
undertakes to study the effects which will be produced by certain
causes, not absolutely, but subject to the condition that other
things are equal, and that the causes are able to work out their
effects undisturbed. Almost every scientific doctrine, when
carefully and formally stated, will be found to contain some
proviso to the effect that other things are equal: the action of
the causes in question is supposed to be isolated; certain
effects are attributed to them, but only on the hypothesis that
no cause is permitted to enter except those distinctly allowed
for. It is true however that the condition that time must be
allowed for causes to produce their effects is a source of great
difficulty in economics. For meanwhile the material on which they
work, and perhaps even the causes themselves, may have changed;
and the tendencies which are being described will not have a
sufficiently "long run" in which to work themselves out fully.
This difficulty will occupy our attention later on.
    The conditioning clauses implied in a law are not continually
repeated, but the common sense of the reader supplies them for
himself. In economics it is necessary to repeat them oftener than
elsewhere, because its doctrines are more apt than those of any
other science to be quoted by persons who have had no scientific
training, and who perhaps have heard them only at second hand,
and without their context. One reason why ordinary conversation
is simpler in form than a scientific treatise, is that in
conversation we can safely omit conditioning clauses; because, if
the hearer does not supply them for himself, we quickly detect
the misunderstanding, and set it right. Adam Smith and many of
the earlier writers on economics attained seeming simplicity by
following the usages of conversation, and omitting conditioning
clauses. But this has caused them to be constantly misunderstood,
and has led to much waste of time and trouble in profitless
controversy; they purchased apparent ease at too great a cost
even for that gain.(4*)
    Though economic analysis and general reasoning are of wide
application, yet every age and every country has its own
problems; and every change in social conditions is likely to
require a new development of economic doctrines.(5*)

NOTES:

1. Schmoller in the article on Folkswirschaft in Conrad's
Handworterbuch.

2. The relation of "natural and economic laws", is exhaustively
discussed by Neumann (Zeitschrift fur die gesamte
Staatswissenschaft, 1892) who concludes (p. 464) that there is no
other word than Law (Gesetz) to express those statements of
tendency, which play so important a part in natural as well as
economic science. See also Wagner (Grundlegung, 86-91).

3. They are discussed in Book V, especially chapters III and V.

4. Compare Book II, chapter I.

5. Some parts of economics are relatively abstract or pure,
because they are concerned mainly with broad general
propositions: for, in order that a proposition may be of broad
application it must necessarily contain few details: it cannot
adapt itself to particular cases; and if it points to any
prediction, that must be governed by a strong conditioning clause
in which a very large meaning is given to the phrase "other
things being equal." Other parts are relatively applied, because
they deal with narrower questions more in detail; they take more
account of local and temporary elements; and they consider
economic conditions in fuller and closer relation to other
conditions of life. Thus there is but a short step from the
applied science of banking in its more general sense, to broad
rules or precepts of the general Art of banking: while the step
from a particular local problem of the applied science of banking
to the corresponding rule of practice or precept of Art may be
shorter still.

Chapter 4

The Order and Aims of Economic Studies

    1. We have seen that the economist must be greedy of facts;
but that facts by themselves teach nothing. History tells of
sequences and coincidences; but reason alone can interpret and
draw lessons from them. The work to be done is so various that
much of it must be left to be dealt with by trained common sense,
which is the ultimate arbiter in every practical problem.
Economic science is but the working of common sense aided by
appliances of organized analysis and general reasoning, which
facilitate the task of collecting, arranging, and drawing
inferences from particular facts. Though its scope is always
limited, though its work without the aid of common sense is vain,
yet it enables common sense to go further in difficult problems
than would otherwise be possible.
    Economic laws are statements with regard to the tendencies of
man's action under certain conditions. They are hypothetical only
in the same sense as are the laws of the physical sciences: for
those laws also contain or imply conditions. But there is more
difficulty in making the conditions clear, and more danger in any
failure to do so, in economics than in physics. The laws of human
action are not indeed as simple, as definite or as clearly
ascertainable as the law of gravitation; but many of them may
rank with the laws of those natural sciences which deal with
complex subject-matter.
    The raison d'etre of economics as a separate science is that
it deals chiefly with that part of man's action which is most
under the control of measurable motives; and which therefore
lends itself better than any other to systematic reasoning and
analysis. We cannot indeed measure motives of any kind, whether
high or low, as they are in themselves: we can measure only their
moving force. Money is never a perfect measure of that force; and
it is not even a tolerably good measure unless careful account is
taken of the general conditions under which it works, and
especially of the riches or poverty of those whose action is
under discussion. But with careful precautions money affords a
fairly good measure of the moving force of a great part of the
motives by which men's lives are fashioned.
    The study of theory must go hand in hand with that of facts:
and for dealing with most modern problems it is modern facts that
are of the greatest use. For the economic records of the distant
past are in some respects slight and untrustworthy; and the
economic conditions of early times are wholly unlike those of the
modern age of free enterprise, of general education, of true
democracy, of steam, of the cheap press and the telegraph.
    2. Economics has then as its purpose firstly to acquire
knowledge for its own sake, and secondly to throw light on
practical issues. But though we are bound, before entering on any
study, to consider carefully what are its uses, we should not
plan out our work with direct reference to them. For by so doing
we are tempted to break off each line of thought as soon as it
ceases to have an immediate bearing on that particular aim which
we have in view at the time: the direct pursuit of practical aims
leads us to group together bits of all sorts of knowledge, which
have no connection with one another except for the immediate
purposes of the moment; and which throw but little light on one
another. Our mental energy is spent in going from one to another;
nothing is thoroughly thought out; no real progress is made.
    The best grouping, therefore, for the purposes of science is
that which collects together all those facts and reasonings which
are similar to one another in nature: so that the study of each
may throw light on its neighbour. By working thus for a long time
at one set of considerations, we get gradually nearer to those
fundamental unities which are called nature's laws: we trace
their action first singly, and then in combination; and thus make
progress slowly but surely. The practical uses of economic
studies should never be out of the mind of the economist, but his
special business is to study and interpret facts and to find out
what are the effects of different causes acting singly and in
combination.
    3. This may be illustrated by enumerating some of the chief
questions to which the economist addresses himself. He inquires:
    What are the causes which, especially in the modern world,
affect the consumption and production, the distribution and
exchange of wealth; the organization of industry and trade; the
money market; wholesale and retail dealing; foreign trade, and
the relations between employers and employed? How do all these
movements act and react upon one another? How do their ultimate
differ from their immediate tendencies?
    Subject to what limitations is the price of anything a
measure of its desirability? What increase of wellbeing is prima
facie likely to result from a given increase in the wealth of any
class of society? How far is the industrial efficiency of any
class impaired by the insufficiency of its income? How far would
an increase of the income of any class, if once effected, be
likely to sustain itself through its effects in increasing their
efficiency and earning power?
    How far does, as a matter of fact, the influence of economic
freedom reach (or how far has it reached at any particular time)
in any place, in any rank of society, or in any particular branch
of industry? What other influences are most powerful there; and
how is the action of all these influences combined? In
particular, how far does economic freedom tend of its own action
to build up combinations and monopolies, and what are their
effects? How are the various classes of society likely to be
affected by its action in the long run; what will be the
intermediate effects while its ultimate results are being worked
out; and, account being taken of the time over which they will
spread, what is the relative importance of these two classes of
ultimate and intermediate effects? What will be the incidence of
any system of taxes? What burdens will it impose on the
community, and what revenue will it afford to the State?
    4. The above are the main questions with which economic
science has to deal directly, and with reference to which its
main work of collecting facts, of analysing them and reasoning
about them should be arranged. The practical issues which, though
lying for the greater part outside the range of economic science,
yet supply a chief motive in the background to the work of the
economist, vary from time to time, and from place to place, even
more than do the economic facts and conditions which form the
material of his studies. The following problems seem to be of
special urgency now in our own country. --
    How should we act so as to increase the good and diminish the
evil influences of economic freedom, both in its ultimate results
and in the course of its progress? If the first are good and the
latter evil, but those who suffer the evil, do not reap the good;
how far is it right that they should suffer for the benefit of
others?
    Taking it for granted that a more equal distribution of
wealth is to be desired, how far would this justify changes in
the institutions of property, or limitations of free enterprise
even when they would be likely to diminish the aggregate of
wealth? In other words, how far should an increase in the income
of the poorer classes and a diminution of their work be aimed at,
even if it involved some lessening of national material wealth?
How far could this be done without injustice, and without
slackening the energies of the leaders of progress? How ought the
burdens of taxation to be distributed among the different classes
of society?
    Ought we to rest content with the existing forms of division
of labour? Is it necessary that large numbers of the people
should be exclusively occupied with work that has no elevating
character? Is it possible to educate gradually among the great
mass of workers a new capacity for the higher kinds of work; and
in particular for undertaking co-operatively the management of
the business in which they are themselves employed?
    What are the proper relations of individual and collective
action in a stage of civilization such as ours? How far ought
voluntary association in its various forms, old and new, to be
left to supply collective action for those purposes for which
such action has special advantages? What business affairs should
be undertaken by society itself acting through its government,
imperial or local? Have we, for instance, carried as far as we
should the plan of collective ownership and use of open spaces,
of works of art, of the means of instruction and amusement, as
well as of those material requisites of a civilized life, the
supply of which requires united action, such as gas and water,
and railways?
    When government does not itself directly intervene, how far
should it allow individuals and corporations to conduct their own
affairs as they please? How far should it regulate the management
of railways and other concerns which are to some extent in a
position of monopoly, and again of land and other things the
quantity of which cannot be increased by man? Is it necessary to
retain in their full force all the existing rights of property;
or have the original necessities for which they were meant to
provide, in some measure passed away?
    Are the prevailing methods of using wealth entirely
justifiable? What scope is there for the moral pressure of social
opinion in constraining and directing individual action in those
economic relations in which the rigidity and violence of
government interference would be likely to do more harm than
good? In what respect do the duties of one nation to another in
economic matters differ from those of members of the same nation
to one another?

    Economics is thus taken to mean a study of the economic
aspects and conditions of man's political, social and private
life; but more especially of his social life. The aims of the
study are to gain knowledge for its own sake, and to obtain
guidance in the practical conduct of life, and especially of
social life. The need for such guidance was never so urgent as
now; a later generation may have more abundant leisure than we
for researches that throw light on obscure points in abstract
speculation, or in the history of past times, but do not afford
immediate aid in present difficulties.
    But though thus largely directed by practical needs,
economics avoids as far as possible the discussion of those
exigencies of party organization, and those diplomacies of home
and foreign politics of which the statesman is bound to take
account in deciding what measures that he can propose will bring
him nearest to the end that he desires to secure for his country.
It aims indeed at helping him to determine not only what that end
should be, but also what are the best methods of a broad policy
devoted to that end. But it shuns many political issues, which
the practical man cannot ignore: and it is therefore a science,
pure and applied, rather than a science and an art. And it is
better described by the broad term " Economics ', than by the
narrower term " Political Economy ".
    5. The economist needs the three great intellectual
faculties, perception, imaginAtion and reason: and most of all he
needs imagination, to put him on the track of those causes of
visible events which are remote or lie below the surface, and of
those effects of visible causes which are remote or lie below the
surface.
    The natural sciences and especially the physical group of
them have this great advantage as a discipline over all studies
of man's action, that in them the investigator is called on for
exact conclusions which can be verified by subsequent observation
or experiment. His fault is soon detected if he contents himself
with such causes and such effects as lie on the surface; or again
if he ignores the mutual interaction of the forces of nature,
wherein every movement modifies and is modified by all that
surround it. Nor does the thorough student of physics rest
satisfied with a mere general analysis; he is ever striving to
make it quantitative; and to assign its proper proportion to each
element in his problem.
    In sciences that relate to man exactness is less attainable.
The path of least resistance is sometimes the only one open: it
is always alluring; and though it is also always treacherous, the
temptation is great to follow it even when a more through way can
be fought out by resolute work. The scientific student of history
is hampered by his inability to experiment and even more by the
absence of any objective standard to which his estimates of
relative proportion can be referred. Such estimates are latent in
almost every stage of his argument: he cannot conclude that one
cause or group of causes has been overridden by another without
making some implicit estimate of their relative weights. And yet
it is only by a great effort that he perceives how dependent he
is on his own subjective impressions. The economist also is
hampered by this difficulty, but in a less degree than other
students of man's action; for indeed he has some share in those
advantages which give precision and objectivity to the work of
the physicist. So long, at all events, as he is concerned with
current and recent events, many of his facts group themselves
under classes as to which statements can be made that are
definite, and often were approximately accurate numerically: and
thus he is at some advantage in seeking for causes and for
results which lie below the surface, and are not easily seen; and
in analyzing complex conditions into their elements and in
reconstructing a whole out of many elements.
    In smaller matters, indeed, simple experience will suggest
the unseen. It will, for instance, put people in the way of
looking for the harm to strength of character and to family life
that comes from ill-considered aid to the thriftless; even though
what is seen on the surface is almost sheer gain. But greater
effort, a larger range of view, a more powerful exercise of the
imagination are needed in tracking the true results of, for
instance, many plausible schemes for increasing steadiness of
employment. For that purpose it is necessary to have learnt how
closely connected are changes in credit, in domestic trade, in
foreign trade competition, in harvests, in prices; and how all of
these affect steadiness of employment for good and for evil. It
is necessary to watch how almost every considerable economic
event in any part of the Western world affects employment in some
trades at least in almost every other part. If we deal only with
those causes of unemployment which are near at hand, we are
likely to make no good cure of the evils we see; and we are
likely to cause evils, that we do not see. And if we are to look
for those which are far off and weigh them in the balance, then
the work before us is a high discipline for the mind.
    Again, when by a "standard rule" or any other device wages
are kept specially high in any trade, imagination set a-going
will try to track the lives of those who are prevented by the
standard rule from doing work, of which they are capable, at a
price that people are willing to pay for it. Are they pushed up,
or are they pushed down? If some are pushed up and some pushed
down, as commonly happens, is it the many that are pushed up and
the few that are pushed down, or the other way about? If we look
at surface results, we may suppose that it is the many who are
pushed up. But if, by the scientific use of the imagination, we
think out all the ways in which prohibitions, whether on Trade
Union authority or any other, prevent people from doing their
best and earning their best, we shall often conclude that it is
the many who have been pushed down, and the few who have been
pushed up. Partly under English influence, some Australasian
colonies are making bold ventures, which hold out specious
promise of greater immediate comfort and ease to the workers.
Australasia has indeed a great reserve of borrowing power in her
vast landed property: and should the proposed short cuts issue in
some industrial decadence, the fall may be slight and temporary.
But it is already being urged that England should move on similar
lines: and a fall for her would be more serious. What is needed,
and what we may hope is coming in the near future, is a larger
study of such schemes of the same kind and by the same order of
minds as are applied to judging a new design for a battleship
with reference to her stability in bad weather.
    In such problems as this it is the purely intellectual, and
sometimes even the critical faculties, which are most in demand.
But economic studies call for and develop the faculty of
sympathy, and especially that rare sympathy which enables people
to put themselves in the place, not only of their comrades, but
also of other classes. This class sympathy is, for instance,
strongly developed by inquiries, which are becoming every day
more urgent, of the reciprocal influences which character and
earnings, methods of employment and habits of expenditure exert
on one another; of the ways in which the efficiency of a nation
is strengthened by and strengthens the confidences and affections
which hold together the members of each economic group - the
family, employers and employees in the same business, citizens of
the same country; of the good and evil that are mingled in the
individual unselfishness and the class selfishness of
professional etiquette and of trade union customs; and of
movements by which our growing wealth and opportunities may best
be turned to account for the wellbeing of the present and coming
generations.(1*)
    6. The economist needs imagination especially in order that
he may develop his ideals. But most of all he needs caution and
reserve in order that his advocacy of ideals may not outrun his
grasp of the future.
    After many more generations have passed, our present ideals
and methods may seem to belong to the infancy, rather than to the
maturity of man. One definite advance has already been made. We
have learnt that every one until proved to be hopelessly weak or
base is worthy of full economic freedom: but we are not in a
position to guess confidently to what goal the advance thus begun
will ultimately lead. In the later Middle Ages a rough beginning
was made of the study of the industrial organism, regarded as
embracing all humanity. Each successive generation has seen
further growths of that organism; but none has seen so large a
growth as our own. The eagerness with which it has been studied
has grown with its growth; and no parallel can be found in
earlier times to the breadth and variety of the efforts that have
been made to comprehend it. But the chief outcome of recent
studies is to make us recognize more fully, than could be done by
any previous generation, how little we know of the causes by
which progress is being fashioned, and how little we can forecast
the ultimate destiny of the industrial organism.
    Some harsh employers and politicians, defending exclusive
class privileges early in last century, found it convenient to
claim the authority of political economy on their side; and they
often spoke of themselves as "economists." And even in our own
time, that title has been assumed by opponents of generous
expenditure on the education of the masses of the people, in
spite of the fact that living economists with one consent
maintain that such expenditure is a true economy, and that to
refuse it is both wrong and bad business from a national point of
view. But Carlyle and Ruskin, followed by many other writers who
had no part in their brilliant and ennobling poetical visions,
have without examination held the great economists responsible
for sayings and deeds to which they were really averse; and in
consequence there has grown up a popular misconception of their
thoughts and character.
    The fact is that nearly all the founders of modern economics
were men of gentle and sympathetic temper, touched with the
enthusiasm of humanity. They cared little for wealth for
themselves; they cared much for its wide diffusion among the
masses of the people. They opposed antisocial monopolies however
powerful. In their several generations they supported the
movement against the class legislation which denied to trade
unions privileges that were open to associations of employers; or
they worked for a remedy against the poison which the old Poor
Law was instilling into the hearts and homes of the agricultural
and other labourers; or they supported the factory acts, in spite
of the strenuous opposition of some politicians and employers who
claimed to speak in their name. They were without exception
devoted to the doctrine that the wellbeing of the whole people
should be the ultimate goal of all private effort and all public
policy. But they were strong in courage and caution; they
appeared cold, because they would not assume the responsibility
of advocating rapid advances on untried paths, for the safety of
which the only guarantees offered were the confident hopes of men
whose imaginations were eager, but not steadied by knowledge nor
disciplined by hard thought.
    Their caution was perhaps a little greater than necessary:
for the range of vision even of the great seers of that age was
in some respects narrower than is that of most educated men in
the present time; when, partly through the suggestions of
biological study, the influence of circumstances in fashioning
character is generally recognized as the dominant fact in social
science. Economists have accordingly now learnt to take a larger
and more hopeful view of the possibilities of human progress.
They have learnt to trust that the human will, guided by careful
thought, can so modify circumstances as largely to modify
character; and thus to bring about new conditions of life still
more favourable to character; and therefore to the economic, as
well as the moral, wellbeing of the masses of the people. Now as
ever it is their duty to oppose all plausible short cuts to that
great end, which would sap the springs of energy and initiative.
    The rights of property, as such, have not been venerated by
those master minds who have built up economic science; but the
authority of the science has been wrongly assumed: by some who
have pushed the claims of vested rights to extreme and antisocial
uses. It may be well therefore to note that the tendency of
careful economic study is to base the rights of private property
not on any abstract principle, but on the observation that in the
past they have been inseparable from solid progress; and that
therefore it is the part of responsible men to proceed cautiously
and tentatively in abrogating or modifying even such rights as
may seem to be inappropriate to the ideal conditions of social
life.

NOTES:

1. This Section is reproduced from a Plea for the creation of a
curriculum in economics and associated branches of political
science addressed to the University of Cambridge in 1902, and
conceded in the following year.